ResearchIs Dehumanizing Animals Possible?

Is Dehumanizing Animals Possible?

It is commonly held within feminist philosophy that dehumanization and objectification are closely related, if not equivalent (see e.g., Cudd 2006; MacKinnon 1987; Dworkin 2000). However, I will show that there is at least one significant distinction between the two: that is, we can objectify non-human animals, but we can’t dehumanize them. On the face of it, this might seem like an obvious claim, for how can we strip something of humanity if it doesn’t have any? However, I want to move away from this response, and claim that there’s actually an interesting and complex reason why non-human animals cannot be dehumanized. This is based on a more intricate understanding of dehumanization: it is not merely a denial or negation of humanity, but rather an exploitation of humanity, based primarily on the mechanism of humiliation. That is to say, dehumanization is a particularly human form of debasement that literally cannot be replicated with non-human animals.

Before elaborating on this point about dehumanization, let’s look at how animals can be objectified. Martha Nussbaum (1995) and Sally Haslanger (2002) have articulated an understanding of objectification as a kind of instrumentalization of the target for the objectifier’s purposes. When this instrumentalization occurs in a non-consensual or unequal relationship (such as the treatment of women within a patriarchal society), it is morally impermissible, but there can also plausibly be forms of benign objectification, where we treat others instrumentally but do not harm them through this interaction. It’s clearly compatible with this definition that non-human animals can be objectified: consider the practices of using chickens and cows as food, of horses and oxen for manual labor, of dogs as drug-sniffers, and so on. These tasks all involve the instrumentalization of animals. There may be varying levels of moral qualms here—e.g., we likely find it more disturbing to use animals as food than to use them to detect illegal or dangerous substances. Nonetheless, these examples share the feature of objectifying the animals involved. What about the dehumanization of animals?

Mari Mikkola (2016) and David Livingstone-Smith (2016) have addressed definitions of dehumanization as the mistreatment of the humanity of the target, or as the indefensible setback of one’s legitimate human interests, e.g., through the assignment of a sub-human essence which purportedly justifies certain mistreatments. However, both Mikkola and Livingstone-Smith move beyond the conception of dehumanization as a simple negation of one’s humanity: for instance, Mikkola cites the practice of wartime rape, and claims that the victimized women are raped in virtue of their social standing in their community—that is, recognition of these women’s social roles as community representatives (i.e., their humanity) is a necessary prerequisite for violating their personhood. Livingstone-Smith makes a related point by citing both Kwame Anthony Appiah (2008) and Adam Gopnik (2006). Appiah writes that, while dehumanizing acts may involve comparing the target to subhuman entities like vermin, “they [still] acknowledge their victims’ humanity in the very act of humiliating, stigmatizing, reviling, and torturing them.” In a similar vein, Gopnik claims that “we don’t humiliate vermin, or put them through show trials, or make them watch their fellow-vermin die first.” Even when someone is performing sadistic dehumanizing acts, they still treat the (human) target differently than they would treat an animal. I claim that humiliation plays a key role here, as the simultaneous acknowledgement and degradation of one’s humanity involved in dehumanization typically manifests itself in humiliating practices meant specifically to attack the target’s humanity—i.e., their dignity, social recognition, and self-respect. Both David Livingstone-Smith (2016) and Richard Rorty (1989), among others, have suggested that humiliation is a uniquely human phenomenon: I will develop this point further to argue that, while we can put non-human animals in humiliating positions, we cannot actually humiliate them. This inability to be humiliated thus explains why we cannot dehumanize animals.

The distinct ‘human-ness’ of dehumanization comes from the fact that humiliation, like embarrassment, is a deeply socially ingrained concept. It requires an awareness of the social role or recognition which one is being denied, as well as an understanding of the humiliating aspects of the particular situation (e.g., the way one is perceived by others). Furthermore, there is a difference, though perhaps not a morally significant one, between being placed in a humiliating position and being ‘properly’ humiliated. Because the latter involves adequate understanding of the relevant social hierarchies, we may be able to place children, severely cognitively disabled humans, and non-human animals in what we recognize to be humiliating positions without their being consciously humiliated. For example, we (as adults, well-inculcated in the practices of our society) might recognize it to be humiliating and dehumanizing for an individual to have their head shaved and to be assigned a string of numbers to replace their given name, or to be forced to stand at the front of a crowd naked. However, it is intuitively plausible that these experiences may vary for children or cognitively disabled people, given their (posited) unfamiliarity with the customs for humiliation. To pump this intuition, imagine these situations as experienced by an infant. It is very difficult to get the intuition that a baby would feel any sense of shame or humiliation at having their head shaved, or at being publically naked, or by being referred to by a string of numbers, even if these acts are performed with the intent of humiliating the child. One explanation for the baby’s lack of the relevant complex emotional response is that they do not yet have a grasp on the social norms and stigmas surrounding these practices. Of course, in reality, some young children and disabled persons can actually be aware of the taboo surrounding these acts, particularly the stigma of public nudity. However, in this scenario, they would fulfill the definitional requirements for humiliation, as they would (at least partially) understand the transgression of the act, and as such, would likely feel shame or embarrassment in association with its performance. As such, it is not impossible for these individuals to be humiliated or dehumanized; however, in most cases, such as the previous example with the baby, they may be placed in a humiliating position and yet not actually humiliated by it, given their failure to recognize the humiliating situation as such. To bring this discussion back to the case of animals: I claim that, given their ignorance with our customs and standards of humiliation, we can place an animal in a situation which we recognize to be humiliating: e.g., by the counterfactual understanding that if I (or another person situated in a similar social position) were to be in that situation, we would be humiliated. But the animal does not (and, likely, cannot, given our inhibited communication with them) have this knowledge. As such, even when we place them in a humiliating situation (by our standards), they do not feel humiliated.

In “Comments on a Contested Comparison: Race and Animals,” (forthcoming in Ethics in the Wake of Wittgenstein , 2019), Alice Crary makes a similar observation about the uniquely human nature of dehumanization. This image, from the 2004 PETA advertising campaign, “Holocaust on Your Plate,” visually compares the plights of factory farmed chickens to those of prisoners in a concentration camp. Crary argues that while both the chickens and the prisoners experience certain harms (e.g., physical suffering, losses of freedom of movement, and destruction to social relationships), the men face a further harm on the basis of their humanity. She writes: “By dispossessing people of all their belongings, shaving their heads, forcing them to live packed together, replacing their names with numbers … speaking to them only in language bereft of conventions connoting respect … and subjecting them to complex regulations while withholding the resources requisite for conforming to them … these technologies aimed at reducing human individuals to a condition in which they were no longer recognizable, even to themselves, as social beings endowed with dignity. This is a very particular condition of debasement to which they were exposed specifically as humans.”

To frame this point in the terms I have been employing, while the prisoners and chickens are both placed in humiliating positions, only the prisoners are actually humiliated by these circumstances, given their recognition and understanding of the social practices from which they were exempt (e.g., practices supporting autonomy, dignity, self-respect) and their knowledge of the significance of the treatment to which they were subjected (e.g., imprisonment, public humiliation, and contemptful treatment). This feature of humiliation allows us to claim that the prisoners are dehumanized by these practices, while the chickens, though clearly mistreated, are not. However, both the prisoners and chickens are objectified in a morally impermissible way.

Charlotte Figueroa

Charlotte Figueroa is a second-year BPhil at University of Oxford. She works primarily in philosophy of language, aesthetics, and feminist philosophy. If you would like to see the full version of this paper, you can contact Charlotte here.

7 COMMENTS

  1. It’s great to see the phenomenon of dehumanization getting the attention that it deserves, so thank you for writing this. But I need to correct your characterization of my position. I don’t see dehumanization as a kind of mistreatment. I see it as a way of conceiving of others which may, and probably usually does, result in mistreatment or complicity in mistreatment. By the way, I do think that other animals can be dehumanized, because I don’t think that the folk-category “human” is, in practice, essentially biological.

  2. This is really interesting and I think the accounts that emphasize the role of humiliation in dehumanization are on to something really important. This also sent me down a rabbit hole of looking up what researchers have said about “self-conscious” emotions (shame, guilt, embarrassment, pride, etc.) in nonhuman animals.

    From that basic research (links below), it seems like no one has found any particular evidence of nonhuman animals feeling embarrassment/humiliation, and one argument for why these might be uniquely human emotions is that they require a more complex theory of mind wherein the animal has a sense of what others are thinking/feeling/perceiving. That’s more than what’s needed for basic empathy, which a bunch of animals have shown evidence of having.

    On the flip side, it seems like all the basic evolutionary ingredients and motivations for embarrassment/humiliation exist in some species, especially primates. They’re highly social and communicative, and they have all the same anatomy that humans have for displaying embarrassment (they have the same facial muscles–though I don’t think any other species blush). One current theory about why humans feel shame, embarrassment, and humiliation is that they basically are kinds of damage control that protect us from further social sanctions. It seems like other highly social animals, where social relationships are super important to them, would also benefit from this sort of damage control. So it doesn’t seem absurd or beyond possibility to think that another species could experience an emotion like humiliation.

  3. The form kept saying my long comment was being flagged as spam, so here’s the rest of it:

    Even if other species do not understand all the same cultural meanings that go into human on human dehumanization, one relevant question might be whether other species can experience the same sort of suffering, and/or damage to their well-being, that humans experience from dehumanization and our particular set of self-conscious emotions. We’re simply uncertain about the answer to that question.

    A follow-up question I find myself thinking about a lot is, in the face of uncertainty about animals’ emotional lives, why is it better to work on the assumption that they don’t ever experience an emotion like humiliation, rather than acting on the possibility that they might–especially for animals we know to be highly social? The status quo is to assume no animals have this emotion, but isn’t that the morally risky thing to do? Aren’t the risks much greater if we assume no other animals feel humiliation–but we’re wrong (and thus cause a metric ton of suffering), vs. the risks of treating them like they might feel humiliation–but they don’t (and thus cause some economic inefficiency from needless precautions?)?

    (PS – In case it sounds like I’d approve of PETA’s ad campaigns, I absolutely don’t and think they’re ignorant, reckless, and exploitative.)

  4. (Sorry for multiple posts: I think my list of references with hyperlinks were triggering the spam filter, so I took out web addresses, unfortunately.)

    References:
    “Emotional communication in primates: implications for neurobiology” Lisa A Parr,1 Bridget M Waller,2 and Jennifer Fugate3

    “The evolution of social attractiveness and its role in shame, humiliation, guilt and therapy” Paul Gilbert

    “Embarrassment: Its Distinct Form and Appeasement Functions”
    Dacher Keltner University of California, Berkeley, Brenda N. Buswell

    “Shame, Guilt, and Depressive Symptoms: A Meta-Analytic Review” Kim S1, Thibodeau R, Jorgensen RS.

    “Emerging Insights Into the Nature and Function of Pride”
    Tracy, Robbins

    “Do Elephants Show Empathy”
    Lucy A. Bates,1 Phyllis C. Lee,2,3
    Norah Njiraini,2 Joyce H. Poole,2
    Katito Sayialel,2 Soila Sayialel,2
    Cynthia J. Moss2 and Richard W. Byrne1,4

    “Can Animals Be Humiliated?”
    Jessica Pierce Ph.D.

  5. Too bad the most important and current book on the topic (TJ Kasperbauer‘s „Subhuman“) is not addressed. It makes some great observations on how dominance may after all play an important role in our dealings with animals.

    That dehumanization requires humiliation seems plain false to me, by the way. People may be dehumanizing me as I speak, without my ever noticing, let alone feeling humiliated. Just as well can we dehumanize babies and the severely disabled.

  6. Dear Ms. Figueroa,

    Given a number of standard assumptions about dehumanization, your argument makes sense. But given that our sense of humanity should involve moral consideration of fellow living beings, to fail to show such consideration may be said to dehumanize us.

    True, then, that failing to consider other animals morally would not dehumanize them, but one might argue that moral consideration for the otherness of other animals, their specifically different living forms, might demand that we do not make them “human” in our eyes, even as a cultural construct of the human. To consider an other animal morally would then be to appreciate it specific differences, its otherness, not its humanness. Not dehumanizing other animals, in this light, is one of the constituents of considering them morally, although it is not sufficient or the whole story.

    Further still, we might understand the sense of humanity as articulating moral relations with other living forms and even with lands, waters, and skies. In this way of seeing things, to fail to morally consider other animals would be to fail the relationships of humanity. It would not dehumanize them, per se, but it would not simply dehumanize only us. Rather, dehumanization would be a distortion in our moral relations of humanity.

    Thank you for your piece.

    Sincerely,

    Jeremy Bendik-Keymer

LEAVE A REPLY

Please enter your comment!
Please enter your name here

WordPress Anti-Spam by WP-SpamShield

Topics

Advanced search

Posts You May Enjoy

Philosophical Mastery and Conceptual Competence

I roughly sort pedagogical issues into two broad categories: engagement and mastery. By “engagement” I mean roughly discussion and reflection on teaching methods that...