Issues in PhilosophyCultivating Philosophical Style

Cultivating Philosophical Style

As a student in an analytic philosophy department in the ’70s and ’80s, I scarcely heard a word about the importance of style. I might occasionally hear that W.V. Quine’s essays were eloquently composed but that grace in his writing was shrugged off as window dressing.

There were professors who complained that a sentence was unclear or the footnotes were done improperly, but that was the extent of their style critiques. They shared the guild conviction that beyond achieving a certain level of clarity, the “how” was of no moment, only the “what.” But the how and the what, the form and the content, are intertwined.

The grand master stylist Nietzsche wrote, “Style ought to prove that one believes in an idea, not only that one thinks it but feels it.” Yes, feels it. Metaphorically speaking  (and when it comes to the inner life, metaphors are all we have), every idea is attached to a feeling and the style of our writing unveils our reasons of the heart, our personal appropriation of the ideas we are tapping out on our word processors.

In his immortal Concept of Anxiety, Søren Kierkegaard, writing under the pseudonym Vigilius Haufniensis, insists that for every subject matter there is a proper mood:

That science, just as much as poetry and art, presupposes a mood in the creator as well as in the observer, and that an error in modulation is just as disturbing as an error in the development of thought, have been entirely forgotten in our times, when inwardness has been completely forgotten, and also the category of appropriation…

The error in modulation alluded to here is clearly an error in mood. On Kierkegaard’s reckoning, an individual who writes about ethics in the frame of mind of someone trying to solve a mathematical equation misunderstands ethics. For Kierkegaard, the mood appropriate to ethical  reflection is an earnest resolve to lead a righteous life. Like Kant, Kierkegaard believed that a knowledge of right and wrong is universally distributed. He was sometimes guilty of underestimating moral complexity; however, he rightly insisted that in adopting an objective attitude to ethics one mistakenly places oneself outside an ongoing question at the core of one’s being.

For those who believe life is an argument and are inclined to curl their lips at the importance of mood, consider how much less powerful Plato’s Euthyphro would be without the irony.

But style in philosophy is more than just a matter of mood. In 1982, Stephen Toulmin published the prescient, “How Medicine Saved the Life of Ethics.” From that time forward, philosophers have assumed the role of experts on the ethics of just about everything—business, engineering, the environment—and presented themselves to the public as consultants on right and wrong.

Nevertheless, if members of the philosophy guild aspire to become public intellectuals,  style must become part of the philosophical curriculum.  We need teachers who will help students develop an ear for what is ponderous and what quickens the heart. We need maestros to encourage students to take Nietzsche at his word: “Style should be suited to the specific person with whom you wish to communicate. (The law of mutual relation.)”

For my part, I begin with the elementary lesson of pruning prose for clichés. After all, clichés are bloodless words, the kind of automatic phrases your email suggests in response to messages. Permit me, then, to call out a few hackneyed terms, beginning with “lens.”

Today it is all too common for a philosophy student to write that he or she will be looking at whatever through the lens of whomever—e.g., in this essay I will be considering Foucault’s Madness and Civilization through a Nietzschean lens. Enough with lenses already! And while we are at it, let’s muffle “echo,” a term echoing through many current philosophical articles, as in, Kierkegaard “echoes” Kant’s understanding of morality.

While the term “embrace” must at one point have possessed a tincture of the lyrical, it too has been bled pale from overuse. The same holds for the not so robust, “robust.”

And yet, the atrophied term that irks me the most is “moves.” Philosophers are always prattling about “moves” as though they were playing a game of chess or preparing a case for court. This tired trope is usually combined with worries to the effect, “If I make such and such a move, so and so will counter with such and such.”

Schopenhauer, who indirectly helped Nietzsche develop an ear and his voice, wrote, “The first rule for good style is to have something to say; in fact, this in itself is almost enough.” Perhaps the “move” metaphor is inspired from the calculating spirit of the grad student who carefully pushes her argumentative pawns: She’s just working the edges of some scholarly problem.

The curmudgeon in me recognizes that someone trying to break into the majors of a tenure track job needs to rack up publications but they shouldn’t get mired in the mentality of thinking of philosophy as a series of moves and counter-moves.

Nietzsche, who once likened the truth to a “mobile army of metaphors,” instructs, “The more abstract a truth which one wishes to teach, the more one must first entice the senses.” Some may read enticing the senses as a form of manipulation, but it is instead an attempt to enrapture the reader’s attention. Philosophy and poetry have a long history of sneering at one another, yet a philosopher who aspires to animate his or her theory would do well to invoke the Muse and dispense with clichés.

Gordon Marino

Gordon Marino is Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Hong Kierkegaard Library at St. Olaf College. His The Existentialist's Survival Guide: How to Live Authentically in an Inauthentic Age will be published by HarperOne in April.

5 COMMENTS

  1. Professor Marino, you say when it comes to our inner life, metaphors are all we have. Ture, but this is the case for all referents, inner and outer. Language, as Heidegger observed, is simply a mode of being in the world. It has no ontological significance in itself. It is simply a projection of our being onto
    what is at hand in this type of a world. Thus, style is a consequence of the meaning of my existence transferred onto the given in nature. This process makes the world ‘my world’. Sartre referred to this as the ‘for me’. In style, we observe the philosophers mode of existence!

    Edward DeLia

  2. Since Nietzsche is the “star” of the post, it might help interested parties to have another take on the implications of style. During the 1980s (a time period relevant to the author, judging from the first sentence of the piece), the author may have passed by a pertinent essay about Nietzsche. The article, “The Politics of ‘The Question of Style’: Nietzsche/Hö[l]derlin” by Geoff Waite, appears in a 1985 collection edited by Mario Valdes, Identity of the Literary Text (U of Toronto P).

  3. There are numerous clichés on the Continental side. I for one will be thankful if I never hear the word “provocative” again.

  4. For me, one of the great masters of philosophical style was Henri Bergson. His writing style is not only connected directly to his philosophy – as should be, but also exemplifies how philosophy can communicate ideas that go beyond words. Bergson himself wrote about philosophical style, for example in his “Introduction to Metaphysics”.

  5. Although the premise of this essay makes progress, it fails to go far enough. It fails to advocate for the kind and extent of style infusion that would effectively attract the general public to academic philosophy. Granted, communicating philosophy through writing that is more aesthetic (as opposed to hyper-technical and ponderous) is a good start. But more is required to attain the mass appeal that a public intellectual captures.

    Personal style (that augments writing style) is the something more. Perhaps my experience is anecdotal and does not accurately generalize to the totality of professional philosophers, but they are, overall, a rather dry and boring bunch, at least according to popular standards. Dry and boring in terms of personal style and thus charisma/magnetism (e.g., clothes, appearance, personality, teaching methodology, interpersonal communication, social engagement, etc. . .). This is not to deny the fact that there are professional philosophers out there that break the austerity mold by virtue of a “cool” personal style. I think, though, that they are the exception. Consider the repute of public intellectuals like Christopher Hitchens, Cornel West, Martin Luther King, Sam Harris, Chomsky, and so forth. You might vehemently disagree with their philosophical “lenses” (or even challenge their philosophical credentials and status as authentic intellectuals), but you would be hard pressed to negate that their stature as public intellectual is a result, in no small part, of their personal style. They (and others figures like them) demonstrate that becoming a superficial hipster is not a necessary condition of cultivating personal style that garners public attention.

    So if members of the philosophy guild aspire to become public intellectuals (or, at minimum, render philosophy more attractive to the general public), they need more than improved writing style, they need a personal makeover. The presentation (or writing style) of philosophy is important to engender more interest, but the personal style of the individual gives the presentation is also important. One without the other just doesn’t get the job done.

LEAVE A REPLY

Please enter your comment!
Please enter your name here

WordPress Anti-Spam by WP-SpamShield

Topics

Advanced search

Posts You May Enjoy

Metaphysics, Colin C. Smith

The syllabus for Metaphysics is the result of my aim to put the “classical” subjects in contemporary metaphysics like personhood, mind, and the potentiality-actuality...