Public PhilosophyBoredom and Injustice

Boredom and Injustice

The emotional price of being poor: How boredom harms those who are less affluent

It seizes us at home or at work, in open spaces or behind closed doors. It sneaks upon us when we are alone or in the company of others, on computers or exercise bikes, while standing up or lying down. It envelops us in buses and on planes, behind the wheel, around the dining table, in poorly ventilated classrooms, and in uncomfortable waiting-room chairs. It’s with us even when we are out of this world. “Funny thing happened on the way to the moon: not much,” wrote Gene Cernan, the last person on the moon.

We are all affected by boredom. Yet not all of us are affected by it in the same way. “Perhaps some of the greatest masterpieces were written while yawning,” Marcel Proust writes in his Remembrance of Things Past, expressing the Nietzschean thought that boredom is the emotional storm before the creative calm. New habits, opportunities, and careers often start with the thought “I’m bored.” But the same holds for unhealthy eating habits, binge drinking, drug use, or utter destruction. “I guess I was just bored,” Keith Eugene Mann said explaining why he ignited two fires in western North Carolina that scorched 16 acres of forest in 2016. “Fact is I had no reason to do it, I just thought … fuck it, life is boring so why not?” posted gunman Ian David Long on social media while killing12 people in Thousand Oaks, California, in 2018.

Researchers have recently learned a great deal about boredom as a psychological and neurological phenomenon. It is studied closely in labs, and sometimes in the real world. Scores of academic papers have been published. Willing participants answer questions in person, in front of their computers, on their phones, at work, even inside fMRI machines. At other times, they are left alone in laboratory rooms, made to watch tedious videos, and asked to perform tiring vigilance tasks, to fold pieces of paper, to copy down lists of references, and even to chase after a mechanical, pink-eyed, jacket-and-scarf-wearing rabbit—all with the hopes of understanding the true character of boredom.

Is boredom first and foremost a cognitive phenomenon? And if so, is it the outcome of our inability to pay attention? “None of this is banal, only if you would attend to it,” Jenny Offill writes in her book Dept. of Speculation, giving literary voice to this idea. Or is the inattention characteristic of boredom derivative, a symptom of an underlying meaninglessness with our situation? Is boredom something more general and slightly more ineffable? Is it an inability to properly make use of our cognitive abilities—“the shriek of unused capacities,” as Saul Bellow memorably puts it in The Adventures of Maggie March? Or is boredom something else entirely? Could it be an unshaped wish, that vague “desire for desires” that Tolstoy mentions? Could it be the result of a physiological disruption, a state of nonoptimal arousal that follows our inability to be stimulated in the right way, as other researchers have suggested? There’s no shortage of views about boredom. If anything, there’s an embarrassment of theoretical and empirical riches.

• • •

I favor a functional view of boredom. This view identifies boredom with a specific role within our behavioral and mental economy. Boredom is an attempted transition from an input state to an output state. It arises when we find ourselves in a meaningless, uninteresting, non-stimulating, or overly stimulating situation—any situation, in fact, for which there’s a perceived mismatch between desired engagement and actual engagement. It reflects a dissatisfaction with our situation and can help us move out of our current state of discontent and into one that is either in line with our interests and values or engaging and stimulating in the right way. Boredom isn’t a perception, a thought, a pain, a distraction, or a sensation. It’s a mechanism for action, a call to move when we’ve become stuck.

The functional view synthesizes a great deal of the literature on boredom. It makes sense of how the different aspects of boredom work together to promote the exercise of boredom’s regulatory function. It generates hypotheses and opens up doors for future research. The functional view also puts to rest the view that boredom is a toxic psychological state, bereft of value. If boredom serves a function, then it can’t be always bad. Indeed, understood as a self-regulatory mechanism, boredom is a boon. It signals the presence of unsatisfactory situations and motivates escape from them. It’s an insurance policy of sorts against the blahs, meaninglessness, and never-ending doldrums.

But we must not draw the wrong conclusion from the functional view. To focus on the positives of boredom without acknowledging its harms is to accept half-truths. These are statements that put a particular spin on our understanding of boredom. They selectively emphasize the positive; they minimize its harms. Half-truths aren’t lies but they still spell trouble. In the case of boredom, string enough of them together and a misleading suggestion arises: the beneficial responses to boredom are available to everyone. The positive gloss on boredom makes it attractive but only by concealing its core. Boredom begins to seem like a good for all, when it should not.

• • •

Boredom is a push for escape, not the guarantee of one. Bring to mind a seemingly never-ending work shift or a mandatory meeting. The boredom they induce is inescapable. Think of Edgar Degas’ ironing women (See photo above). They stand exhausted, oppressed by labour and the monotony of their task. They are bored. And they are forced to remain so until their work concludes. The feeling of boredom won’t suffice to get us out of our discontent. We must also have the resources, freedom, time, and energy to do so.

Even when boredom motivates change, it’s not necessarily for the better. Boredom is functional, yes, but it isn’t a remedy for all of life’s ills. Our responses to boredom can be beneficial or harmful, moral or immoral, profound or mundane. Boredom is an instigator of change—a felt provocation to take action and to respond to a perceived crisis of agency. Through its affective, cognitive, volitional, and physiological features, boredom calls on us to do something other than what we are currently doing.

All the same, it never reveals to us what that something else is. And it doesn’t fabricate opportunities when those don’t exist. Without access to the right source of alternative engagements, and without guidance as to what might be worth pursuing, it is easy to choose the wrong way—sometimes the only way—out of boredom. It’s no surprise that maladaptive responses to boredom abound. This is especially true for those of us who find ourselves often in the grips of boredom, distressed and bedraggled by its force. Binge drinking, drug use, gambling, mindless eating, self-harm, even disobeying social distancing measures can all serve the function of avoiding the doldrums of life. They don’t serve a greater purpose and may even lead us back to boredom. Yet they offer us a much-needed, albeit temporary, respite from ennui.

If we lack the material and psychological resources to properly respond to boredom’s onset, it can become a burden and threat to our well-being. When boredom finds us in a place of stress, of dependency on others, of poverty, of loneliness, we stand psychologically compromised. Our capacity to respond to boredom is undermined, and we are less likely to alleviate it in productive ways. It affects most severely those who, because of no fault on their own (their psychological, social, or material standing), have a hard time escaping productively out of boredom. In this way, boredom can be unjust.

The nature of its injustice becomes discernible when we turn our attention to how boredom works in conditions of material scarcity. Decades of research on the psychology of poverty have shown that poverty affects self-regulatory processes, coping styles in response to stress and difficult situations, decision-making, mental and physical health, and even our beliefs about the efficacy of our actions. Worse still, research has found that poverty puts one in an almost inescapable bind: Poverty influences our psychology and behavior in ways that further harm us financially.

Conditions of material scarcity are an especially fecund ground for the experience of boredom. In poverty, we are often incapable of choosing our means of livelihood. We are restricted in the manner in which we carry out the activities that we are forced to carry out. We lack the ability to change jobs, to move, to take breaks, to relax, to decompress. There’s no opportunity to learn an instrument or to travel. There’s no time to gaze lazily at the starry night. Our attentional resources are consumed by worries and thoughts of monetary scarcity. And we experience less control and greater dependency on external factors. All of these conditions are known antecedents of boredom.

Poverty not only invites boredom but also corrodes our ability to face up to it. Poverty takes a toll on our self-regulatory abilities and impairs mental and cognitive functioning, especially when it comes to decision-making. In doing so, it has the capacity to derail our coping mechanisms and to even further solidify our vulnerability to boredom. In poverty, boredom can become cruel and unjust—a scourge that afflicts those who are the least capable of dealing with it.

• • •

Poverty doesn’t appear to be unique in escalating the harms of boredom. Other conditions that exert prolonged and severe stress on us—loneliness, chronic pain, psychological dependency—may lead to the same worrisome outcomes. But none of this contradicts the functional account. It rather highlights the need to keep in mind the bivalence of boredom.

An overly optimistic presentation of boredom generates unrealistic expectations. It obfuscates its dangers. It can even assign blame for our failure to cope productively with boredom when often such a failure is beyond our control. An excessively pessimistic picture is also flawed. It leads us to underappreciate boredom, perhaps even to fear it. It robs us of the opportunity to make use of our rich emotional life. It doesn’t permit us to listen to boredom when it needs to be heard. It doesn’t allow us to be motivated by it when we are in need of its push.

Our words about boredom matter. They shape the discourse of boredom and in doing so, influence our expectations concerning its experience and outcomes. If we want to get boredom right, we must describe it evenhandedly.

Photo: “Women Ironing” by Edgar Degas (via Wikimedia Commons)

Andreas Elpidorou

Andreas Elpidorou (@aelpidorou) is associate professor of philosophy at the University of Louisville. He specializes in the philosophical study of the mind and has published on the nature of emotions, consciousness, and cognition. His most recent book, Propelled: How Boredom, Frustration, and Anticipation Lead Us to the Good Life (Oxford University Press, 2020), explores how negative emotions and states of discontent can help us live a flourishing life. His work on boredom has been featured in venues such as BBC News, Forbes, Nautilus, Fast Company, Vogue, Business Insider, Huffington Post, and others, and he has made appearances on both radio and television.

1 COMMENT

  1. ‘[Participants] are left alone in laboratory rooms, made to watch tedious videos, and asked to perform tiring vigilance tasks, to fold pieces of paper, to copy down lists of references’

    Guess what. This is what the work most people, and almost all women, do is like. What is commonly known as ‘real work’ is a pure, stinking, miserable hell of boredom. Work is hell, a hell of boredom and for most there is no way out.

    Keynes predicted in the 1930s that by the year 2000 the standard work week would be 15 hours. But we’re still stuck on the work ethic, promoting more jobs, more work, instead of finding a way to share the wealth so that fewer people have to work and that those who do work less.

    And what infuriates me most is the betrayal of feminists, obsessing about abortion and sexuality issues when occupational sex segregation, which is especially high in occupations that don’t require a college degree, hasn’t diminished since the 1990s. Pink-collar work is the most physically-confining, repetitious, and agonizingly boring. Imagine cashiering: you’re confined to a 2’ x 2’ space scanning groceries, and that is what you do 8 hours a day 5 days a week, and will do for most of your adult life. Or data-entry: you’re trapped in a carrel inputting data, with every keystroke monitored. For women, unless we catch the brass ring (as I have) this is what our lives are like. It is no longer economically feasible or socially acceptable to drop out of the labor force altogether: this is the work most of us do for most of our adult lives.

    Yeah, lousy men’s jobs are lousy too—and physically exhausting. But not this bad. Wouldn’t you rather be a mobile carpet-and-grout cleaner, tow-truck driver, or exterminator than a supermarket checker trapped in that 2’ x 2’ space? Wouldn’t you rather be an upholsterer or ditch-digger that than a child care worker under surveillance where the helicopter parents monitor you online so that you can’t just stick the little stinkers in front of the TV and do something else? And even if you wouldn’t choose tow-truck driving or ditch-digging, over cashiering or childcare, I would: people should have the option of choosing the misery they find least-worst.

    Women don’t prefer those boring pink-collar jobs. During the natural experiment of WWII, the overwhelming majority women working at ‘non-traditional jobs’ surveyed by the Women’s Bureau said they would prefer to keep them if they could. But, of course, they couldn’t so it was back to the check-stand and the typing pool for us.

    One of my first papers published long ago in Hypatia of all places and more recently revised and anthologized (I changed ‘keypunch operator’ to ‘data-entry operator’) was ‘How Bad is Rape’ https://philpapers.org/rec/BABHBI in which I argued that ‘being raped is bad, but being a keypunch operator is much worse’. And I stand by that. I’m no Cartesian dualist but I’d say that ethically, not metaphysically, I am my mind, not my body. Harms to the body, including sexual assault, are external to the Self, to the core of who I am. The real rape, most serious harm to the self, is being forced to do boring pink-collar work—which is the lot of most women. And I have been raped.

    Unfortunately, those who know don’t speak, and those who speak don’t know. Feminist activists, largely privileged white women, do not get it. They do not think, as I do every time I go through a supermarket checkout or visit an office in my university where women at computers are doing boring clerical work, ‘this could easily have been me’. So, feminist activists: why don’t we have some action here, so that most women aren’t confined to these agonizingly boring jobs?

    And let’s leave the peculiarly stinking situation of women aside. Most work is agonizingly boring. No chance to solve puzzles, to achieve, to learn. Not even the chance to exert energy. Work is pure, stinking, miserable hell—you are on the rockpile. I know—I once had to do it. Short of sickness and death itself, the two greatest evils of the human condition are poverty and drudgery. But, for some reason I don’t understand, while most people recognize the badness of poverty, they don’t recognize the badness of drudgery, the misery of boring work.

LEAVE A REPLY

Please enter your comment!
Please enter your name here

WordPress Anti-Spam by WP-SpamShield

Topics

Advanced search

Posts You May Enjoy

APA Member Interview: Rami El Ali

Bio: Rami El Ali works on the philosophy of perception, technology, and phenomenology. He is currently pursuing a second PhD focusing on virtual reality...