How We Think about the Life & Practice of Philosophy, part I
Long enough ago that it is almost ancient history, I had a disturbing experience. It was negative at first, but later it made me think, and the upshot was interesting. In this brief post, I’d like to share it with you, with apologies in advance for not nailing down the issue technically in this short space.
Here was the experience. I had been looking forward to a new book about to appear. I admired the philosophical imagination of the author and what I took to be their moral sensibility. But when I read the book’s preface, I was jolted. The author fabricated a story of their intellectual itinerary, subtly but surely, erasing what I had known to be the presence and role of a real philosophical community out of which the author’s philosophical vision had developed. This community had supported and encouraged the author. Not just a few of the imaginative directions in the book could be traced back to the community and the preoccupations, work, and style of many of the people in it. Instead of recognizing this community and bringing what it had to offer into discourse, the author painted a picture of themselves as individualistic, intellectually precocious, and daringly original.
Although my sense of the author’s honesty was shaken, the interesting thing that emerged over time was the question of whom and what we recognize when we narrate our own work and its development. It is common in academia to name-drop or to tell a story about oneself so that one secures the kind of recognitional position that one wants or needs. But it’s not clear to me that academics regularly recognize the real philosophical sources of their development. Even more interesting than why we might not do that is the question of what we might gain by doing that. What could it mean for philosophy to make a practice of recognizing the real philosophical communities that form us in philosophy? It would mean, I think, a subtle but real shift in our sense of philosophy and so of our practice of it.
*
By a “real philosophical” community, I mean a community in which the people involved care for each other and each other’s “searching” through their “sense of life” (two expressions I take from the introduction to Love’s Knowledge by Martha Nussbaum). “Searching” is more prosaic than “philosophizing,” but it seeks insight. “Sense of life” is more capacious than “reason,” although it involves making sense. A real philosophical community, like love, is known by its fruits: we come to search better through our sense of life, or we develop a fuller, finer sense of life.* Real philosophical communities leave us as we age with memories of having actually gone somewhere in our sense of life, of having grown up, or of having come to appreciate how to live well in a more insightful way. They mark our time in real philosophical time.
What would it be to recognize real philosophical communities in our teaching and writing? Asking this might be said to beg the question of whether real philosophical communities deserve a place in philosophical teaching and writing. One might think that real philosophical communities are really philosophical and so could have many connections with philosophical teaching and writing. But academic philosophy often follows one of two paths: either (1) it teaches critical thinking, or (2) it contributes to knowledge as research does. These each give us pause to recognize real philosophical communities in our teaching and writing.
- It’s common to understand critical thinking as a set of skills. A community where people care about each other’s searching through their sense of life hardly seems needed for it. Such a community might even interfere with critical thinking. Real philosophical communities sound touchy-feely, not critical.
But how can I subject premises and the logic employing them to withering scrutiny if I do not search through them intensely even to the point of abandon, losing my ego a bit (or a lot) in the process? Searching seems needed, and a community that supports it seems deserving. How, too, can I deal with the many tricky ways that people frame arguments rhetorically, often manipulatively, if I do not have much of a sense of life? The big picture, the live sense of living seems needed to put things in context and to see what is really going on with speech-acts. But if that is so, communities cultivating our sense of life seem important. Even if we think philosophical teaching and writing are basically about conveying critical thinking, real philosophical communities seem deserving of a place in philosophical teaching and writing. - The case may seem harder to make with research university practice. Philosophical research isn’t personal, and it isn’t remotely about my life. One’s not searching; one’s researching. There’s a difference. Knowledge, not living, is the quarry. How to resolve this objective problem, not how to involve this subjective person, is the query.
Yet what is philosophical research about? It’s about such things as how we should live, how to think about how we should live, how to think, how to think about how we think, what knowing is, how to know what knowing is, etc. The things we research concern and depend on the way we search in our sense of life. At the very least, many – if not all – topics of research could use our developed sense of life and our being in touch with searching. The communities that actively develop these in us would be needed.
So let us say that real philosophical communities do, on a first go, deserve a place in how we think about the life and practice of philosophy even when teaching critical thinking or writing up our research. The question then is, what place?
*
To recognize real philosophical communities in our teaching and writing would do, I think, some subtle and powerful things. Let me start with teaching. When a classroom works, it is for a semester a real philosophical community, one that often lingers on in some of its members for years, even decades – sometimes for life. Many philosophy teachers are already good at helping the class see that what we are doing here, right now, is the real thing, philosophy! Philosophy is not out there in the books and we are in here, subservient to the golden wisdom of the authorities. No! We are together actively helping each other search in our sense of life.
Less common is for teachers to ask of students to turn to their real philosophical communities outside of class and to draw on these to inform the substance of class. When I studied early childhood education, something like this was common: the work inside the classroom explicitly called on involving families outside the classroom. Except for some practices in feminist philosophy and cultural studies, however, it’s not common to see “school-family relationships” in philosophy classrooms, neither in discussions, nor in assignments.
Think about assignments first. What would it be to weave real philosophical communities into assignments? One thing it might do is to bring philosophical texts and arguments into contact with philosophical life (and vice-versa). Another thing it might do is to hone relating as a mark of good writing and thought. Not simply analytical acumen or scholarly thoroughness would make for good writing or thought for class. No, the ability to relate what we analyze or study to the texture of our lives would become equally important.
Or think about discussions in class. Bringing real philosophical communities into class discussion would emphasize the relatedness I’ve just highlighted. But it would also expose everyone in the class to a myriad of ways to search in our sense of life, each conveyed by those relaying them with “knowing emotion” (to use Rick Anthony Furtak’s expression). Asking students to draw on their real philosophical communities would make class more social and less cut off from everyday life and student experience. It wouldn’t do these things by watering down philosophy to make it more palatable. It would actually increase focus and rigor by considering what exactly makes something philosophical. This critical pressure would be exerted not just on each other and on ourselves but also on the vaunted texts and arguments we read together. Could this go some way to undermining epistemic erasure in high Eurocentric philosophy as well? (It might.)
*
Recognizing real philosophical communities in writing is possibly more interesting. I suspect that this is because philosophical writing has often indulged in its own mythology, projecting a refined community elsewhere than where and how people actually search in their sense of life. Recognizing real philosophical communities might imply demythologizing philosophy by way of the quotidian. It might also undermine academic pretentiousness by leading us back to vital subcultures. Here’s how:
To write involving real philosophical communities could affect what we focus on. It would bring us closer to sociology. Would we write about great philosophers or entirely difficulty and important problems and arguments? Yes. But we’d also write about these things in relation to the places where we actually sort out some of their connections, premises, or logic. We might write about political theory, but also about our role in community politics. We might consider thorny problems in epistemology, but also how they appear when we raise a child and see their mind bloom. We might think about Plato in his life and put it alongside politically traumatized teenagers in our lives seeking esoteric knowledge, if not the Pythagorean occult.
Writing involving real philosophical communities could also change how we write. Perhaps we would write in such a way that we share what we do with our real philosophical communities as part of the compositional process. Perhaps their view would matter when we compose our texts and would become part of the critical review process for us. Or how our real philosophical communities speak might enter into our language, diversifying academic speech. Our audiences might change, too. We might begin to write so that real people are addressed while we nevertheless try to explain the universal significance of a problem to an imagined public.
Most of what I’ve sketched are subtle and complex shifts. Still, they seem grown up, emotionally and intellectually worthy (or so says my sense of life). In rereading them, I am happy that many people in philosophy already regularly do some version of these things I’ve advocated or something very much like them. I guess I’m just asking that we don’t keep real philosophical communities on the low down anymore.
~
Part 2 can be found here.
* As Nathan Eckstrand points out, some communities that appear to have a view about what wisdom is often corral their members into conformity. “Follow our wisdom!” they imply with every correction, omission, avoidance. True enough. But to be able to search shatters conformity eventually. How can I search if I am not free enough to try things out? And to have a sense of life depends on room to roam enough to develop that sense (so we can intelligibly say of someone very young or very rigid, “they do not have a sense of life … yet”). A real philosophical community cannot be a view where wisdom is settled, one way or another. True to the kind of thing Kierkegaard said pseudonymously in Concluding Unscientific Postscript (well, until his confession of authorship at the end), the searching is the truth of philosophy even as one searches for the Truth.
Small changes to simplify the title and create the header were made June 2022.
Thanks much for this article. I appreciate it very much. I am very intrigued with the idea of philosophical communities . . . and I have a question:
In your closing sentence you say: “True to the kind of thing Kierkegaard said pseudonymously in Concluding Unscientific Postscript (well, until his confession of authorship at the end), the searching is the truth of philosophy even as one searches for the Truth.”
I would like to find where Kierkegaard says this. Can you be specific about the exact location where K says this in CUP ? Best wishes to you.
Hi Rick, I am sorry that I missed this ages ago. I did not sign up for notifications! I am paraphrasing the very broad idea of CUP that “truth is subjectivity.” SK knew that this was on the face of it an absurd idea, easily contested. But I take it that he was thinking not of accuracy but of truth as a process of uncovering things that actually make sense to oneself. Here he modernizes alethia. That’s how I understand it, but I am not a SK scholar. The Cambridge handbook on the CUP might be a good place to see how mistaken I am! With best wishes, Jeremy