by Sarah Tyson
The place of women in the history of philosophy tends to be most interesting to people who already have an interest in feminist philosophy. This is not universally the case. Mary Warnock, for instance, edited a book, Women Philosophers, in which she argues that feminist philosophy isn’t really philosophy. Warnock’s book seems to be for those who want to be reassured that a few women can be sprinkled into the history of philosophy without anything having to change. But one might also, despite Warnock’s framing, think it strange that such a volume were necessary. If women could be included without much fuss, and these women should have been, then why weren’t they? Whence the need for a book about women philosophers? Not surprisingly, for the most part, the gateway drug to engagement with historical women thinkers is some sort of dalliance with feminism. In other words, historical women are mostly interesting to people who already find the relationship between women and a lot of things strange.
This correlation is important but also problematic. After all, feminism poses the threat of destabilizing the academic discipline of philosophy—someone advocating feminism might raise “issues” that have to be “addressed.” Historical women, on the other hand, do not usually come across as threatening. They seem sort of grandmotherly or statuary—if they appear at all. Their histories might include shocking biographical details, but these have a tendency to seem quaint to modern readers in a way that feminism does not. To be clear, historical women should be seen as threatening, because to be remembered at all, they must have stepped way out of line. But to have to point this out constitutes part of the problem. It indicates that there’s already another narrative taking up most of the air waves. For women in the history of philosophy this narrative is roughly: there weren’t any—or at least not any that were really doing philosophy.
Many women throughout history have asked some tough questions about the everyday business of their lives—and occasionally got arrested for it, or killed. And it seems that questioning the ordinary (not to mention being arrested or killed for it) is one important thing shared by feminism and philosophy. According to this reading, philosophy and feminism ought to be good friends, and philosophers would, of course, have feminist impulses given their desire to question. But this desire to question is also shaped by social and cultural forces that likely truck in sexist impulses. For this reason, professional philosophers don’t necessarily have any commitment to or even grudging respect for feminist methods, practices, and questions. So long as it’s just feminists, and not philosophers more generally, who care about these women and their moxie, the discipline of philosophy will remain unreconstructed and the worse for it.
My point is not that women have contributed to every philosophical question we grapple with today (although I would contend they have) or made intellectual interventions worth our time and attention (again, I would bet on it). Rather, my point is that a presumption thrives within philosophy that there were not (and are not) women whose contributions need to be considered, and when feminists insist otherwise, the response, if not hostile, is often an embarrassed politeness. Embarrassed politeness is an extremely effective defense. The embarrassment arises from a sense that a mistake has been made and the politeness from a desire to survive the moment with dignity until one can guffaw later, preferably with friends. This logic goes so deep that for a lot of folks, the matter is settled not just without a review of the evidence, but also with a sense of certainty that there is no evidence to review.
I wish this were all hyperbole.
So long as the vast majority of people who are recognized as philosophers think that historical women thinkers can be “dealt with” by feminists, we won’t know where we’ve come from as a discipline or what might be possible. Disregarding women is one of the most reflexive, everyday things a person can do. That disregard wasn’t born overnight and its practices have been refined for generations. Without understanding the history of that disregard and how it operates, we risk, almost to a certainty, being swept along with it. We might be disgruntled or sorry or well-meaning or politely embarrassed about the whole thing, but we’ll also be complicit.
Philosophy as a discipline has all sorts of (non-philosophical) tricks for policing its borders. Philosophy as a practice offers us tools, methods, approaches, and, when we’re lucky, an attitude of iconoclasm that are really good for challenging everyday assumptions, practices, feelings, and judgments. Through philosophy, we can discover that the very category of “women” is, itself, a production partly (although by no means fully) of misogyny. Can we still use the category? Sure. Ought we have long conversations about it? Yes, which is exactly what feminists have been doing. Should we be forever suspicious of it? I’m leaning towards probably, although “forever” is admittedly a long time. Can the category of women be deployed in ways that make the everyday seem strange? There’s a whole archive of trans* (usually feminist) scholarship that does just this, so don’t take my word for it.
The point in thinking about the intersection of feminism and philosophy is not only to do justice to historical women who have been excluded from our consideration. Rather the point is to gain traction on our own time. How have women been absented? Why? What have the effects of this missing history been? And what about the unrecoverable history—the women whose thoughts cannot be found, no matter how hard we scour all the archives we can think to look for? To avoid merely seeking vindication for what we already know (and thereby offering justification for what already is and the silences by which it has been built), we need methods to unsettle our disciplined expectations. Such powerful methods have been developed within feminist philosophy.
My book brings methods for thinking about women’s exclusion developed by Genevieve Lloyd, Luce Irigaray, and Michèle Le Doeuff into conversation with the work already done to reclaim historical women for the discipline of philosophy. I argue that women cannot be effectively reclaimed so long as norms and practices that made their exclusion possible persist. So, reclamation must be a process of transforming philosophy. That is, to engage with historical women as philosophers, we will need to change the practices and norms by which we identify what work is worthy of philosophical attention, why, and for what ends. I found the most radical and productive method in Le Doeuff’s approach, especially because, unlike many theorists of women’s exclusion (including Lloyd and Irigaray), she often turns to historical women thinkers to open up new ways of thinking about contemporary problems. She does so by considering what life now might be like had historical women’s interventions gained traction in their own time. What might our present lives be like if women’s ideas had not been systematically absented?
All of this leads me to consider two texts, which to many folks trained in philosophy, but not feminism, will look far afield: The Declaration of Sentiments and Sojourner Truth’s speech in Akron, Ohio, in 1851. The first is the inaugural text of the women’s rights movement in the US, while the second is a heavily mythologized speech by an itinerant preacher who stole herself from slavery. Truth’s vision of the women’s movement challenges not just the women’s rights advocates in her own time, but also to much contemporary feminism. That is, the vision of The Declaration meets an even more radical vision in Truth’s response. When Truth said, “I am a woman’s rights,” she handed us a puzzling relationship between subject and predicate that still deserves our attention. She asked us to consider the nature of rights that could be inhabited by a former slave who could not read and who was guided by an inner voice that she understood to be divine. While The Declaration drafted in Seneca Falls, New York, proposed ways to address many of the limits to women’s freedom, it did not offer a critique of the category of “women.” Without such a critique, they risked reinforcing prevailing norms of race, class, and property (at least). Truth upheaved that category with her intervention. Such an upheaval cannot be sprinkled into history without anything changing.
It’s not that I mind having the most productive and exciting conversations about this work with people who take feminism seriously—that’s been one of the greatest gifts of my work, actually. It’s just that even after all this time studying women’s exclusion from philosophy, it is still so strange to me that those are not conversations I can have with the vast majority of professional philosophers.
Thank you to Geoffrey Adelsberg, Andrew Dilts, Amy Hoffman, Gillian Silverman, Carl Tyson, and Toni Tyson for comments on an earlier draft of this blog.
Sarah Tyson is Associate Professor of Philosophy and affiliated faculty of Women and Gender Studies at the University of Colorado Denver. She is the author of Where Are the Women? Why Expanding the Archive Makes Philosophy Better(Columbia University Press, 2018) and co-host of the podcast New Books in Philosophy.
Thankfully, there is more and more excellent work being done on the many women philosophers of the past! I’m so pleased to see that the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy has entries on Émilie du Châtelet, Anne Conway, Mary Wollstonecraft, Mary Astell, Harriet Taylor Mill, and others. The APA Diversity and Inclusion Syllabus Collection is also a good sign!
I agree! Those are great resources from which I have learned a lot. I’m so grateful to the people who have made them available.
This article, like all articles, should be paired with another article which makes an opposite case. Here’s a quick example…
I’ve been using many different online philosophy forums regularly for more than 20 years. Online philosophy forums are very democratic and inclusive, almost anybody can join and share almost anything they wish to say.
Every single one of these philosophy forums has been overwhelmingly dominated by men, even though there is no attempt at all to discriminate against women, or even really any way to know what a member’s gender is unless they share that information given that most members use anonymous screen names.
So what we see in this case is a philosophy environment where it’s not even possible to discriminate against women, and men are still in a large majority.
It seems entirely possible that the world of academic philosophy has long been dominated by men for the very same reason, generally speaking on average, men are more interested in philosophy than women are.
No, this is not because men are smarter. I would argue it’s more a case of the opposite being true, but I’ll leave that argument for another day.
The question I’d like to see addressed is, how does one get through a college level philosophy education without knowing anything about online philosophy forums, which provide such a ready example to counter feminist victim claims in regards to the academic philosophy business?
If most of the college courses are being taught by men, and these male instructors have failed to make this case, then ok, in that case there would be just cause for complaints.
Hi Phil, Thanks for reading the blog and responding. Would you explain a little more about how you’ve given an opposite case to the case I’m making? I’m not sure how the tendency of online philosophy forums to be dominated by men speaks to the issues I’m raising about the relationship between philosophy and feminism.
Sarah, sorry, I just came across your request today, two years late.
You ask “How have women been absented?”
My reply was that women have not been absented from philosophy forums, they have largely chosen not to participate. That seems a wise choice, one I often wish I’d made.
I’m now exploring philosophy groups on Facebook (I’m a slow learner) where it’s much easier to determine the gender of posters. Again, philosophy posters on Facebook are overwhelmingly men, just like on forums.
I’m just suggesting that to some degree women have indeed been excluded from the field of philosophy, and to some degree they have willingly chosen not to participate.
Dear Sarah, Thank you very much for your post. As someone who is deeply committed to the recovery of women philosophers in the history of philosophy, I found what you say very interesting, and I agree with you that the relationship between feminists and historians bears examination, and that what counts as doing philosophy needs rethinking. I haven’t read your book yet, although I am looking forward to doing so, but there was something about the way you framed matters in your post that bothered me. You write that the standard view is that, historically speaking, there were no women doing at least what counts as philosophy. My concern is that while this might have been true twenty or thirty years ago, in recent years there has a lot of work being done on recovering the work of women in the history of philosophy. I am not going to list names because when I say a lot I mean a lot. As result of this work it is pretty well understood that there are a great many women to be found in the history of philosophy. Inasmuch as much although not all of this work was done by women, you way of framing your issue has the effect of erasing a lot of work done by women philosophers today. Surely it is not appropriate to protest the absence of some women by ignoring others. As I say, I haven’t read your book and perhaps you deal with my worry there but in the meantime I did want to raise my worries.
Dear Margaret, Thank you for reading the post and responding to it. There has been a great deal of reclamation work done in the past several decades (I think of Mary Ellen Waithe’s development of A History of Women Philosophers as the inaugural event of this field in Anglophone philosophy). And I do spend a great deal of the book considering what has happened within that field. What I hoped to accomplish in this post is to point to the way that this important work still seems to be mostly of concern to people (of any gender) who work in and on feminism, as well as to shed light on why I think that isolation is a problem. This work can be quite challenging to many dominant norms and practices within the contemporary discipline, but I see a quite effective disregard of those challenges in the form of unexamined beliefs that seem to thrive in many disciplinary spaces that historical women’s work isn’t of general concern. I wanted to point to the way the work of historical women remains the concern of a subfield—one that is counted on to deal with one of philosophy’s “diversity problems” without anything much having to change in the discipline. So, I think (and intended) that my post acknowledges and relies on the work that you pointing to, as well as calls for more attention to it. All that said, I take the critique of erasing women’s work quite seriously—and I am particularly interested in identifying how people can do this even in the guise of inclusion. So, I would like to hear more about how you think my framing does this.
Dear Sarah, Thank you very much for your thoughtful reply. I think like Charlotte I am more optimistic about the changes that have been taking place in the study of women in the history of philosophy. I wonder if in part my optimism stems from focussing on the subfield on history of philosophy, where I hang out, whereas perhaps you are interested in philosophy more generally. But as I said before, I need to read your book in order to get a better sense of your approach to these matters. Best, Margaret
Thanks, Margaret! Your optimism means a lot to me. Best, Sarah
Dear Sarah, I have acquired for myself a copy of your book and while I have not had time yet to read much of it, I have read enough to realize that in it you are not denying that reclaiming women for the history of philosophy has taken place but instead are critically examining the methods of reclamation. Is this right? If so, then it may well turn out that we have disagreements, How not? but I think I have a better sense of what our disagreements will be over.
A reader! Thank you for taking the time, Margaret. I’d love to hear your disagreements and other thoughts.
Fascinating work. These are issues with which I am grappling as well. I have your book on my bedside table, and am eager to return to it once I fully make my way into summer. Thanks for your important contributions to this really important line of scholarship.
Thanks so much! I am excited to read your new Metaphilosophy piece.
Hi Sarah,
Thanks for underlining that the heavy lifting of inclusion of women philosophers in the philosophical canon and/or the history of philosophy has largely been done by feminist philosophers, and in a relatively short stretch of time. I can’t avoid some optimism though when I recall my graduate education and early days in philosophy and how things have changed
Sarah, this is a really fantastic post! I want to assign it in my classes for reading. I gently differ with Margaret Atherton’s impression of the way you frame things, although I think it’s simply that I’m completely in the bag for your framing: I take you to be saying that of course there has been work done in recent years of recovering the names of philosophical women, and writing women more accurately into their deserved locations in the history of philosophy, but that this work is still considered the hobby horse of some feminists rather than a widely appreciated necessity on the part of all philosophers. I too have increasingly come to find it bizarre that the disregard of women in the history of our sort of study is still shrugged at by most philosophers as an accident of history. I especially appreciate your description of “embarrassed politeness” as a defensive response on the part of philosophers today. I recall very clearly entering philosophy in the 1990s – I earned my BA in another field so I didn’t deeply study philosophy until I was thinking about graduate school, and the extent to which women were excluded was striking to me, as were the words of men who spoke for and about us in the history of philosophy. My instructors either omitted all the passages in which canonical men said anything about women from our required reading, or with Embarrassed Politeness advised us to “just ignore that part.” The project of ignoring what may be better met with attention and reconsideration remains a live one, and your excellent essay here articulates the persistence of that determined, polite ignorance.
Thanks so much, Kate. I love Feminist Philosophy Quarterly. Thanks so much for creating spaces where transformative work can happen.
Hi Charlotte, Your optimism means a lot! Your work changed my understanding of what the practice of philosophy could be. Thanks you for making so much possible.